HOW SOCIOLOGICAL THEORY SHAPED OVER TIME

To understand what sociological theory is, we must distinguish it from other explanations of social life. Sociological theory or explanation relies on evidence from the senses and from the social world itself to arrive at its conclusions. Another important distinction is between sociological theory and ideology. Ideology involves value judgments about what is good or bad, right or wrong, better or worse. We will discuss how many theorists also have ideologies, although they may not state them explicitly. Social ideology, as in politics and other aspects of social life, include liberal, conservative, and radical. A theorist who argues, that society is held together by agreement on the rules and by our mutual need for one another is very likely basing her or his theory on the conservative ideology that “what is, is good.”
Social theory or Sociological theory
Sociological theory is the aspect of sociology that students often find the least compelling. Although some sociological theory can be accused of unnecessary complexity and abstraction, it is theory that underpins the “interesting” sociological discussions. In essence, theory is nothing more than sociologists’ generalization’s about “real” social interactions and the everyday practices of social life.
Theorizing is and always has been a part of everyone’s way of thinking. Every time you try to guess why a group of people act in a particular way, you are theorizing about a social phenomenon on the basis of your own knowledge of reality.
Let us discuss what sociological theory in understanding with different concept:
The Contours of Sociological Theory
All human beings attempt to make sense of their world and their place in that world. It does not simply react to our situations in the world, we theorize about them. We reflect upon, interpret, and most important, represent symbolically our actions and interactions.
As Karl Marx pointed out, bees construct complex dwellings, but what distinguishes the “poorest architect” from the “best of bees” is that the architect constructs the building in his/her imagination before constructing it in reality.” Sociological theory is an abstract, symbolic representation of, and explanation of, social reality. Sociological theory talks about guidelines for thinking in a disciplined manner about the social world.
Deductive and Inductive Reasoning
The sociological theorist may start with an idea, or theory, about the nature of society and social behavior and proceed to construct in relatively abstract, symbolic terms some sort of model that can explain social life. That is, the sociologist may theorize as follows –
Deductively is a proceeding from the general to the particular. Alternatively, the sociologist may observe some interesting but puzzling feature of social life and, examining the social context of the puzzling feature, derive a general explanation, or theory, about this particular social puzzle. The theory formulated by this procedure is arrived at inductively.
Ideology and Objectivity
Ideology is commonly thought of as a set of ideas that justifies judgments about good/bad, superior/inferior, better/worse. Furthermore, when applied to individuals or groups, ideology is thought to assert or legitimize the power of some group over another. On the other hand Ralf Dahrendoft asserts the problem of ideologies within sociology is endemic to the sociological project. From the beginning, sociology had “two intentions.”It was supposed to help us to understand society by using objective, “scientific” methods; at the same time, it was supposed to help individuals achieve “freedom and self-fulfillment.”
Karl Mannheim (1929) characterized the difference between these two aspects of ideology as the difference between particular and total ideologies.
Particular ideologies involve systems of knowledge that deform or conceal facts.
Total ideologies are systems of knowledge tied to the social/historical place and time of the individuals who espouse them, irrespective of good or bad intentions. The belief in the inherent superiority of a particular race as the basis for the organization of social relations is an example of a total ideology.
Sociological Subjects
Max Weber stated that objectivity was an “impossible obligation” but one that sociologists must assume. The problem is in good part a result of the fact that sociologists themselves are both subjects and objects of sociology. As subjects (sociological theorists), they aspire to a detached or objective view of society; as objects (human beings), they are rooted in a particular society and have personal beliefs about it.
Research Traditions
Sociological research traditions make assumptions about how the social world is organized and how it operates and how human beings can know that world. Generally, sociologists can be classified as positivists, idealists, or critical theorists. In practice, however, aspects of two or three research traditions may be combined in the work of any particular theorist.
Positivism. Early in the development of sociology, some theorists assumed that the social world could be studied in the same manner as the natural world and that social laws could be formulated much like the laws formulated in natural science to describe the behavior of physical phenomena. This approach is usually called positivism.
Idealism. The positivist tradition is often contrasted with idealism. The idealist is less concerned with searching for universal laws than with understanding or interpreting meaning. In addition, the idealist assumes that meaning is not an immutable law but is historically changeable.
Critical Theory. The third tradition, critical theory, is far more antagonistic to positivism than to idealism. Critical theory rejects altogether the idea that knowledge can be objective—that is, abstracted from human interests and practices. Whereas positivism can reveal how to reach certain goals but is morally indifferent to the goals themselves, critical theory aims to reveal what those goals should be and how they can produce a better society.
The Philosophical Precursors of Sociology
Recognition of the dual role of sociologists resulted from the idea that society itself could be the subject of scientific scrutiny. This idea had its origins in the eighteenth century and led, in the nineteenth century, to the establishment of sociology—a term coined by Auguste Comte (1798-1857).
Sociology differed from these other accounts was in recognizing that society is a separate, discrete entity, that it is amenable to scientific investigation, and further, that it is an entity constructed by human beings and therefore subject to variations and change.
At the onset of Western modernity, various intellectuals promoted the positivist idea that the social world could be understood in the same terms as the physical world of nature because of the human capacity of reason. Understanding the social world through the exercise of human reason, they assumed, would reveal the social laws to be followed to achieve social progress and human perfectibility.
These intellectual developments were connected with various transformations of the traditional social world to a modern world, which became particularly evident in Western societies starting in the eighteenth century. In essence, sociology emerged as a way of explaining and dealing with the problems and dislocations accompanying the gradual transformation to modernity in Western society. Social observers were particularly concerned with such characteristics of modernity as capitalism, industrialization, bureaucratization, the division of labor, urbanization, nationalism, imperialism, democracy, and individual rights and freedom.
Tradition and Modernity
In the Western medieval, feudal world, the interconnections of material, human, and divine existence were expressed in the idea of the Great Chain of Being. This idea, endorsed and promoted by the Church, ranked the physical, the human, and the divine in a hierarchy, with rocks at the bottom, God at the top, and “man” occupying the space just below the angels.
The first tentative changes in this view began in the Renaissance of the fifteenth century, with a shift from the idea of God as the supreme creator of nature to the idea of God expressed in the laws of nature. Many intellectuals came to believe that these laws could be discovered by human beings through mathematics. This idea had profound implications for science as well as art.
Eighteenth-century Enlightenment thinkers known as the philosophes used this new wealth of comparative data on societies to construct a theoretical basis for a decisive challenge to traditional socio-religious theory and ideology. As a twentieth-century observer noted, “the advance of knowledge, whether devout Christians liked it or not, meant the advance of reason”.
The Philosophes and the Enlightenment
Enlightenment thinkers put society and social relations under intense scrutiny. Their central interest was the attainment of human and social perfectibility in the here and now rather than in some heavenly future. They considered rational education and scientific understanding of self and society the routes to all human and social progress. Such progress was assured because all human beings have the faculty of reason. Reason need only be educated and exercised without any arbitrary restraint, whether of tradition, religion, or sovereign power. As you will see later, however, some human beings were still excluded as less rational than others and therefore in need of control. The excluded were generally women, nonwhites, children, and the lower orders or classes. Nevertheless, the philosophes claimed that educated individuals would exercise their critical reason for their own happiness and, by extension, the happiness and welfare of society as a whole.
Political Revolutions
Enlightenment social and political thought paved the way for revolutionary ruptures in traditional social relations. From the Renaissance on, western European societies acquired modern characteristics, but Enlightenment ideas and the American, French, and Industrial revolutions ushered in some of the definitive characteristics of modern capitalist society. The profound upheaval of the French Revolution, in particular, highlighted some of the problems and issues of concern to prerevolutionary Enlightenment thinkers. These became the problems and issues of the “new science,” sociology, at the beginning of the nineteenth century.
Subjects and Citizens
Both the American and the French revolutions were possible in part because subjects had gradually been transformed into citizens. In traditional societies, all members are subjects of the ruler, who derives authority from custom and tradition, usually divine custom and tradition. Resistance to any particular ruler is difficult because power resides in the institution of rulership. Consider the phrase “The King is dead, long live the King.”
Resistance to traditional authority became more possible with the dissemination of the ideas of Thomas Hobbes, John Locke, Montesquieu, Jean Jacques Rousseau, and Mary Wollstonecraft. Their work contributed to the gradual transformation of subjects into self-governing citizens.
Thomas Hobbes (1588-1679)
He view, human beings are governed by a selfish and “perpetual and restless desire for power after power” (1651:49). This lust for individual power continues until death. Anarchy—”every man against every man”—is curbed only by the fact that men fear death. As all men are rational, they may be convinced to adopt “convenient Articles of Peace” in order to avoid social anarchy and death.
John Locke (1632-1704)
Locke postulated that individuals were in a “State of perfect Freedom” and a “State also of Equality” before the formation of the state. This free and equal state was not a “State of Licence” because it was governed by the law of nature as embodied in reason. The law of nature, or reason, “teaches all Mankind . . . that being all equal and independent, no one ought to harm another in his Life, Health, Liberty, or Possessions”. Because all were free and equal in the original state of nature, “no one can be put out of this Estate, and subjected to the Political Power of another, without his own Consent.”
Montesquieu (1689-1775)
Montesquieu argued that all human beings are social beings and that to seek the origins of society in the presocial dispositions of human beings, as Hobbes and Locke had done was futile. To understand society, one must observe the facts of society, just as the natural scientist observes the facts of the physical world.
Through observation, social theorists could find the law-like patterns of social relations, similar to the laws of cause and effect discovered by natural scientists. In his preface to his De Vesprit des lois, Montesquieu remarked, “I have not drawn my principles from my prejudices, but from the nature of things.”
Montesquieu distinguished three types of government—republic, monarchy, and despotism—on the basis of his observations and comparisons of various societies.
Montesquieu, whose methodology was historical and comparative, is considered a cultural relativist. He suggested that the laws of nature apply to all, but that they take on different forms and expressions according to the form of government—as well as according to climate, soil, the geographical size of the country, the number of inhabitants, and the social factors of religion, customs, and the economy. The laws that govern a nation are therefore an expression of the general “spirit’’ of the nation; they define the “originality and unity of a given collectivity.”
Jean-Jacques Rousseau (1712-1778)
Rousseau claimed that private property brought about war, conflict, and thus the need for a civil state, noting “there is scarcely any inequality among men in the state of nature.” The inequality “that we now behold owes its force and its growth to the development of our faculties and the improvement of our understanding, and at last becomes permanent and lawful by the establishment of property and laws.”
Mary Wollstonecraft (1759-1797)
Wollstonecraft opened A Vindication of the Rights of Woman (1792) with the statement that she would consider women “in the grand light of human creatures, who, in common with men, are placed on this earth to unfold their faculties”. Both men and women have the faculty of reason, and if women’s reason were not cultivated alongside men’s, women would “stop the progress of knowledge and virtue”.
Capitalism and Industrial Revolution
The industrial transformations were fueled by earlier capitalist developments, beginning in the sixteenth century, and together they generated new social and political arrangements. The urban middle classes were becoming a significant social force, and “free” wage workers were becoming the standard in a competitive, largely unregulated marketplace. By 1780, the industrial revolution had appeared in Great Britain. France, the United States, and later Germany also underwent industrial transformation in the early nineteenth century.
The “new society” that industrialism produced was not an overnight phenomenon, but it marked the definitive end of ideas about the Great Chain of Being and the social order that such ideas represented. Class relations replaced hierarchies of rank and status in importance, and the wealth acquired from industry and trade became as significant as land and title to claims of power and authority. Most important, the middle classes became more numerous and more important in the political control and direction of the state.
The forced migration to the cities and wage labor in factories permanently changed lifestyles. In an agrarian society, household production and agricultural work generally involved all members of the family, including children. When men, women, and children went to work in the factories, however, the family livelihood was no longer a collective enterprise. Each member of the family was employed and paid as an individual worker. The situation was particularly difficult for women, who had been able to make adjustments in their household activities in an agrarian setting to accommodate child care but could not in the factory context. But everyone resented the loss of independence, a resentment increased by the overwhelming power that capitalist employers had gained over employees.
Order and Change
In the midst of the profound social and economic transitions of the industrial revolution, the American and French political revolutions occurred. Many social theorists had initially welcomed these upheavals of the traditional social order, but their zeal for change was tempered by sober analysis of the disruptions that accompany revolution.
The Enlightenment philosophes all wanted to see the end of arbitrary, despotic government and the institution of rational regimes based on law reflecting empirically established social facts. For example, Rousseau had proposed a more revolutionary solution than Montesquieu, but both thinkers were convinced that enlightened reason could produce a good society of free, rational, cooperative citizens. The work of Edmund Burke in England and Louis de Bonald and Joseph de Maistre of France stands in conservative contrast to these theorists.
Edmund Burke (1729-1797)
As a privileged Englishman, Edmund Burke wanted no revolution in Britain. He considered tradition, custom, hierarchy, and subservience the basis of good government. He believed that any reform, or change of any sort, was not to be undertaken lightly. Like Montesquieu, Burke believed that political authority must be tailored to the particular social and historical circumstances and that any changes must be slow and carefully worked out. Politically, Burke considered prudence the “primary virtue of civil government”. Burke (1790) described his reactions to the French Revolution as “alternate contempt and indignation; alternate laughter and tears; alternate scorn and horror”. His Reflection on the Revolution in France (1790) explicitly rejected radical change in favor of the preservation of traditional hierarchy and customary authority.
Louis de Bonald (1754-1850) and Joseph de Maistre (1754-1821)
Like Burke, Louis de Bonald and Joseph de Maistre viewed the French Revolution as a disaster and viewed social, political, and economic relationships in the aftermath of the Revolution as destructive to social order and harmony. De Bonald and de Maistre’s conservatism was, however, different from that of Burke. Whereas Burke wanted to conserve the status quo, de Bonald and de Maistre, living in postrevolutionary France, wanted to bring back the “good old days” of monarchy and religious authority. De Bonald believed that the development of modern industry and capitalism had undermined the divine social order, and he regarded medieval society as the ideal society. Both de Bonald and de Maistre saw modern life as especially destructive of the traditional—that is, patriarchal—family, which they believed formed the cornerstone of a stable, ordered state. De Bonald was opposed to what he regarded as the anarchic individualism.
De Bonald and de Maistre considered that society was made by God not men. The divine link and the long historical chain of tradition and custom had established the superiority of society over the individual. The basic social institutions of the Church, the state, and the patriarchal family were all based on God’s will, and therefore the individual should subordinate self to these institutions and to the traditions associated with them.
Science and Ethics
Conservative reactions to the momentous changes in social life were in large part reactions to the perceived absence of traditional moral standards in society. The secularization of society, conjoined with a faith in science and objectivity, did produce a problem for intellectuals: how to secure an ethical basis that could guide practical actions. Key issues for classical sociologists were determining the basis for notions of the “good society” and determining the essence of human nature that prompts individuals to act ethically. Efforts by philosophers Immanuel Kant and Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel to deal with these questions form an important background to the work of early sociologists. Their theories also inform contemporary debates about the sociology of knowledge.
Immanuel Kant (1724-1804)
How the rational, autonomous individual could be a moral being without appealing to some external divine connection was addressed by the philosopher Immanuel Kant. He was influenced by Rousseau but disagreed with Rousseau’s idea that the essence of human nature could be discovered in the pre-social state of nature. Human nature, in Kant’s view, is defined by the ability to transcend and oppose nature through the exercise of both reason and moral standards.
The man of reason and morality becomes a sovereign subject and is free, Kant believed, whereas “natural” man is an object determined by sensory experience and is unfree. As he stated in his essay “Was ist Aufklaäring?” (“What Is Enlightenment?”), “All that is required for this enlightenment is freedom; and particularly the least harmful of all that may be called freedom, namely the freedom for man to make public use of his reason in all matters”. As both natural beings and rational subjects, human beings are therefore free to be immoral or moral. Although society may encourage moral action, it cannot determine or guarantee such action, because human beings have free will.
Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel (1770-1831)
Individual progress toward pure reason and absolute freedom is accomplished dialectically, in Hegel’s view. That is, as individuals reflect upon themselves and their situation, they are able to contradict and go beyond what has been acceptable in the past and thus reach a new level of understanding. More important, in the pursuit of freedom or emancipation, individuals achieve an understanding that demands social change. Because of this dialectical process of give and take, a person’s ethics come to reflect those of the larger society and, at the same time, shape society’s ethics.
Hegel’s idealism was an important corrective to the belief that the social world could be understood scientifically in the same manner as the natural world. Reason to him was not an impersonal, a historical force but an historically situated product of human reflection. His legacy for sociology was the idea that society and human beings cannot be studied as objects like the objects of natural science. Sociologists need to understand the subjective meaning of social actions, bearing in mind that sociologists bring their own a priori understandings to the inquiry. That is, sociologists cannot help but have evaluative or normative stances regarding the topics they study; they cannot avoid ideology.
Final Thoughts on the Philosophical Precursors
According to both reactionary conservatives seeking to bring back the “good old days” and radicals wanting to overthrow the status quo in favor of a better future, the revolutions of the eighteenth century had introduced a host of problems into the social world: disorder, alienation, insecurity. However, other social theorists were more sanguine about the revolutions, believing that they had brought scientific rationalism and autonomous individualism, which were the bases for individual freedom and the construction of an equitable society. The status quo conservatives believed that this post-revolutionary, modern society was self-corrective; the liberals believed that it was good but could be improved through conscious effort.
Sociology emerged out of these theoretical and ideological debates as a science that could explain modern social life. In fact, the Enlightenment discovery of “society” as an independent, scientifically understood entity with a reality apart from its individual members was the fundamental concept that led to the development of the specialization that Comte called sociology.

Post a Comment

Previous Post Next Post